Utilitarians And Lawbreaking: When Does The End Justify The Means?

do utilitarians believe in breaking the law

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that asserts that the morally correct action is the one that produces the most good. Utilitarians believe that the purpose of morality is to make life better by increasing the amount of good things (such as pleasure and happiness) in the world and decreasing the amount of bad things (such as pain and unhappiness). This is a form of consequentialism, which states that the rightness or wrongness of an action is determined by its consequences.

Utilitarianism is associated with philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, who identified the good with pleasure, and so were hedonists about value. They also held that we ought to maximise the good, or bring about 'the greatest amount of good for the greatest number'.

However, utilitarianism has been criticised for its implications, such as the idea that it is acceptable to break a promise if it brings about more good. Some utilitarians have sought to modify the theory to accommodate these objections, such as by adopting ''rule' utilitarianism, which permits a particular act to be judged right or wrong according to whether it keeps or breaks a useful rule.

lawshun

Utilitarianism and the law: Utilitarianism is a moral theory that determines right from wrong by focusing on outcomes

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that determines right from wrong by focusing on the outcomes of actions and choices. It is a form of consequentialism, which is a doctrine in ethics that evaluates actions based on their consequences. Utilitarianism holds that the most ethical choice is the one that will produce the greatest good for the greatest number.

The theory was developed in the 18th and 19th centuries by British philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill, who were critics of common law. Bentham sought to simplify the law by translating the language of rights and obligations into a pain-pleasure calculation. He believed that all human behaviour is motivated by a desire to maximise pleasure and avoid pain.

Utilitarianism promotes "the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people". It is a reason-based approach to morality, but it has limitations. For example, it does not account for feelings, emotions, culture, or justice. It also struggles to predict whether the consequences of our actions will be good or bad, as they occur in the future.

There are two types of utilitarian ethics: rule utilitarianism and act utilitarianism. Rule utilitarianism helps the largest number of people using the fairest methods possible, while act utilitarianism makes the most ethical actions possible for the benefit of the people.

lawshun

Utilitarianism and justice: Utilitarianism has trouble accounting for values such as justice and individual rights

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that asserts that the rightness or wrongness of an action is determined by its outcomes. It is a form of consequentialism, which holds that the morality of an action is determined by its consequences. Utilitarianism, specifically, focuses on the good and bad results of an action.

While utilitarianism is a reason-based approach to determining right and wrong, it has some limitations. One of the main limitations is that it struggles to account for values like justice and individual rights.

For example, consider a scenario where four people in a hospital require organ transplants to survive: a heart, lungs, a kidney, and a liver. If a healthy person walks into the hospital, their organs could be harvested to save four lives at the cost of one. This scenario would arguably produce the greatest good for the greatest number of people. However, few would consider it an acceptable or ethical course of action.

This example demonstrates the challenge that utilitarianism faces in reconciling its focus on maximizing overall happiness with the protection of individual rights. In this case, the utilitarian approach would prioritize the greater good over the rights of the individual, which could lead to a violation of justice and individual liberty.

Another criticism of utilitarianism is that it tends to create a black-and-white construct of morality, with no shades of grey. It does not account for feelings, emotions, or cultural differences, and it cannot predict with certainty whether the consequences of our actions will be good or bad.

In conclusion, while utilitarianism offers a relatively simple method for deciding the morally right course of action, it faces challenges in addressing values such as justice and individual rights, as well as the complexities and uncertainties inherent in human behavior and society.

lawshun

Utilitarianism and punishment: Utilitarians believe that punishment is a form of government-imposed pain

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that holds that the rightness or wrongness of an action is determined by the balance of good over evil that is produced by that action. The theory is associated with British philosophers, economists, and political thinkers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill.

Bentham and Mill believed that all human behaviour is motivated by a desire to maximise pleasure and avoid pain. They also believed that the law is often written in vague terms of rights and obligations. Bentham thought that the law could be simplified by translating the language of rights and obligations into a pain-pleasure calculation.

Utilitarians have tried to apply Bentham's hedonistic calculus to criminal law. They assert that punishment is a form of government-imposed pain. They also believe that criminals break the law only because they do not fully comprehend the confusing language of rights and obligations. Utilitarians conclude that the law must be stripped of such confusing terms and redrafted in language that equates socially undesirable conduct with pain and socially desirable conduct with pleasure.

Utilitarians measure the desirability of human conduct by the amount of happiness it generates in society. They maintain that the ultimate aim of any law should be to promote the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. Utilitarians would permit conduct that produces more happiness in society than unhappiness and would proscribe conduct that results in more unhappiness than happiness.

In determining whether a punishment is justifiable, utilitarians will attempt to anticipate the likely consequences of carrying out the punishment. If punishing an offender would most likely produce the greatest balance of happiness over unhappiness compared with the other available options (not taking any action, publicly denouncing the offender, etc.), then the punishment is justified. If another available option would produce a greater balance of happiness over unhappiness, then that option should be chosen and punishment is unjustified.

Utilitarians have traditionally focused on three ways in which punishment can reduce crime: deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation. Firstly, the threat of punishment can deter potential offenders. Secondly, punishment can incapacitate offenders by confining them for a certain period, thereby reducing their ability to harm others during that time. Thirdly, punishment can rehabilitate offenders by improving their character so that they are less likely to re-offend.

However, there are other ways in which punishment can affect the balance of happiness over unhappiness. For example, whether or not a given offender is punished will affect how society views the governmental institution that is charged with responding to violations of the law. The degree to which people believe this institution is functioning justly will clearly affect their happiness. Utilitarians are committed to taking into account every consequence of a given punishment insofar as it affects the balance of happiness over unhappiness.

Trump Foundation: Lawful or Criminal?

You may want to see also

lawshun

Utilitarianism and intent: Utilitarians may distinguish the aptness of praising or blaming an agent from whether the action was right

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that asserts that an action is right if it promotes happiness and wrong if it produces unhappiness. However, utilitarians may distinguish between the correctness of an action and the aptness of praising or blaming an agent. This is because utilitarians believe that the moral quality of an action is determined by its consequences, rather than the motive or intention behind it.

For example, consider a person who saves someone from drowning in 1938, who later turns out to be Adolf Hitler. Saving a drowning person is generally considered the right thing to do, and the rescuer would be praised for their action. However, if the negative consequences of this action are considered (i.e., the millions of lives lost due to Hitler's actions), utilitarians may argue that the action was wrong, despite the good intentions of the rescuer.

This distinction between the evaluation of an action and the evaluation of the person performing it is important in utilitarianism. While the rescuer's action may be deemed wrong in hindsight due to its negative consequences, it would be unfair to blame or criticise the rescuer, as they could not have foreseen the future impact of their actions.

This example highlights a disagreement among utilitarians about whether judgments of right and wrong should be based on the actual consequences of actions or their foreseeable consequences. "Actual consequence utilitarians" argue that the rescuer's action was wrong, while "foreseeable consequence utilitarians" maintain that the rescuer did the right thing because they could not have predicted the negative outcomes.

In summary, while utilitarians believe that the moral correctness of an action depends on its consequences, they may distinguish this from the question of whether an agent deserves praise or blame, which takes into account the agent's intentions and foreseeability of outcomes.

Trump's Ethics: Did He Break the Law?

You may want to see also

lawshun

Utilitarianism and the greater good: Utilitarianism promotes the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people

Utilitarianism is a moral theory that asserts that an action is right if it results in the happiness of the greatest number of people in a society or group. It is a form of consequentialism, which evaluates the moral correctness of an action based on its consequences. This theory was developed by British philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill in the 18th and 19th centuries.

Utilitarianism holds that the most ethical choice is the one that will produce the greatest good for the greatest number. This is often referred to as "the greatest happiness for the greatest number" or "the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people." This principle of equality was radical and progressive in Bentham's time, as it was commonly accepted that some lives and some people's happiness were simply more important and valuable than others. Bentham's principle of equality makes the government responsible for creating policies that would benefit all equally, not just the elite.

Utilitarianism is a reason-based approach to determining right and wrong, but it has limitations. One limitation is that it tends to create a black-and-white construct of morality, with no shades of gray. Another limitation is that utilitarianism cannot predict with certainty whether the consequences of our actions will be good or bad, as the results of our actions occur in the future.

Additionally, utilitarianism struggles to account for values like justice and individual rights. For example, consider a scenario in which a hospital has four patients whose lives depend on receiving organ transplants. If a healthy person wanders into the hospital, their organs could be harvested to save four lives at the expense of one life. This would arguably produce the greatest good for the greatest number, but few would consider it an acceptable or ethical course of action.

In conclusion, utilitarianism promotes the greatest amount of good for the greatest number of people by focusing on outcomes and consequences. While it has limitations, it provides a relatively simple method for deciding the morally right course of action in any particular situation.

Frequently asked questions

Written by
Reviewed by
Share this post
Print
Did this article help you?

Leave a comment